ATEG Archives

May 2013

ATEG@LISTSERV.MIAMIOH.EDU

Options: Use Monospaced Font
Show Text Part by Default
Show All Mail Headers

Message: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]
Topic: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]
Author: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]

Print Reply
Subject:
From:
Bruce Despain <[log in to unmask]>
Reply To:
Assembly for the Teaching of English Grammar <[log in to unmask]>
Date:
Fri, 24 May 2013 11:33:59 -0700
Content-Type:
text/plain
Parts/Attachments:
text/plain (1 lines)
Sergio, Herb, et al.,



I think the following concepts are important and will interest you.  Any not interested in the philosophy of grammar can always disregard these comments.  I hope that what I say here will not in any way discourage others from using this listserve for communicating and understanding pedagogical methods better that are more central to its purpose.  I hope you will understand that as I grow older I feel a need to share some of the learnings that have enriched my study of English.  



I think there is an important point to be made when it comes to analysis in general and grammatical analysis in particular.  In general there is a distinct dichotomy to be aware of between the analysis of things into parts and of things into classes.  Componential analysis is in terms of the part-whole relationship (meronomics).  This is the concentration on constuents (phrase structure, syntax).  Categorical analysis is in terms of the class-subclass relationship (taxonomics).  This is where the idea of prototype is particularly important.  Whenever a class-subclass is conceived to exist it is possible to posit a new class between them to relate to the one as a subclass and the other as a superordinate class.  Different cultures have done this in very different ways and science often finds new classes of objects not yet appreciated as such.  Linguists will also find that different cultures have different ways of analyzing discourse despite the fact that some of them are committed to finding just one way to describe them all.  



The continuum you speak of is related to taxonomy.  We can attempt to find a continuum in meronomics, but will constantly find that we must share the same system with another for communication to be successful.  I think that your six levels of a language's representation of the part-whole relationship that are described by syntax, will be found to correspond to the ways that the elements (leaves and branches) of a complex hierarchal constituent tree can relate to one another.  Those that are close together (local relations) can often be omitted, but are understood (virtual) when the structure is interpreted.  Our analysis of these meronomic relationships will then correspond to a certain measure of closeness within the language.  In English the relationship of number between subject and verb is not often very local.  Nor is the relationship denoted by case.  With number there is an obvious correspondence with the semantics of the noun phrase, but different languages will handle it differently, e.g. Chinese.  With case there is an even less obvious correspondence with certain semantics of the verbs and objects mentioned in the sentence, and these are even more obviously handled differently from language to language, e.g., Finnish.  I think that it is in the realm of these not-so-local syntactic relationships that the semantics of languages vary the most.  



In my work I have come to be very committed to keeping the semantics of the meronomics and the semantics of the taxonomics apart.  Some examples may make this idea clearer.  In the syntax we have nouns, but we also have pronouns.  These two parts of discourse are different leaves of the noun phrase branch, but either may be head.  The adjective may attach to the noun phrase branch, but not as a head.  Noun phrases, adjective phrases, or adverbial phrases may be attached to the verb phrase in a predicate.  Articles, demonstratives, and identifiers are like adjectives in having leaves and branches attached to the noun phrase.  



The place of these elements as part of discourse is distinct from the semantics of their taxonomics.  For example, the articles, demonstratives, and identifiers are for making reference to objects.  In the verb phrase there are certain (auxiliary) verbs for making reference to modes (modals), aspects, time, etc.  English keeps these two reference functions separate because of the two different functions assigned to nouns and verbs.  The same semantic feature of reference has taxonomic importance on an auxiliary (verb) and on an article (adjective).  



A prototypical noun, say "thing" or "person," is one that does not require additional branches to function as head of a noun phrase.  Similarly a prototypical verb, say "do" or "make," may be the sole head of a predicate phrase.  In order to communicate more precisely, these prototypes must be replaced by nouns, viz., verbs, of less general denotation or combined with more branches and leaves of other types.  



Bruce



--- [log in to unmask] wrote:



From: Bruce Despain <[log in to unmask]>

To: [log in to unmask]

Subject: Re: relative "that" revisited

Date:         Wed, 22 May 2013 07:52:10 -0700



Sergio,



I for one very much enjoyed your excellent comments and eagerly await Herb's response. 



I believe that the "that" of the noun clause subordinator may almost always be dropped.  The example in your last sentence also allows dropping, but may be stylistically lacking:   



"So it is possible, cognitively speaking, the absence of “that” as a subordinator does not create any difficulty/ambiguity in our perception of the sentence."



The relative pronoun "that" may be (informally) dropped when it is an object in the subordinate clause. My bringing up the headless-relative clause was because the "what" may be (informally) dropped when the clause is subject and used as predicate in the subordinate clause. 



Bruce





--- [log in to unmask] wrote:



From: sergio <[log in to unmask]>

To: [log in to unmask]

Subject: Re: relative "that" revisited

Date:         Wed, 22 May 2013 13:10:34 +0200



Herb,

Now, I see your point better. I apologize for the length of this

comment in advance.

And again, it is primarily to clarify the matter for myself, rather than else.

I have broken down my argument and the final goal is the statement in

the first section.



FROM ARISTOTELIAN CATEGORIES TO COGNITIVELY PLAUSIBLE ONES

As to the ongoing discussion about the status of "that" in relative

clauses, I think that most of the difficulties rest on the

Aristotelian categorizing system, which is often called the necessary

and sufficient conditions. Not only does relying on such a

categorization system engender many logical aporias, but it has also

been proven rather unrealistic since psychologist Eleanor Rosch's

studies in cognitive processes involved in category/concept building

in the 1970s.

After her studies a more cognitively plausible system of

categorization, named semantics of prototypes, has been recognized to

explain more efficiently many "oddities" in the way we put objects

under one category or the next.

Basically, all this is to state what Craig has posted on May 9, "I

think it's more a matter of where we draw the boundaries with our

definitions...I also grow impatient with approaches to grammar that

imply there are strict rules about how language can act."



THE COMPOSITE NATURE OF RELATIVE CLAUSE MARKERS

In a prototypical way, the issue of the status of "that" could be

restated as follows:

the objects that can be used to introduce a relative clause have a

more or less apparent pronominal function. Using “marker” as a neutral

term that encompasses “subordinator,” “complementizer,” or “pronoun,”

we can build a continuum as follows:

1) Zero marker = NO pronominal feature, Japanese does not have any

marker at all to introduce relative clauses.

2) Omissible marker = close to null pronominal feature, like "that" in English.

3) Marker sensitive to some semantic trait of the antecedent = light

pronominal feature, like the opposition “who-that” in English.

4) Marker sensitive to the syntactic function in the relative clause =

heavy pronominal feature, like the today almost superseded opposition

“who-whom,” the opposition “qui-que” in French ("qui" for subject,

"que" for non-subject function) or German's relative markers that are

case sensitive.

5) Marker sensitive to the presence of a preceding preposition =

Heavier pronominal feature, like in the opposition “that-which” in

English ("The knife with which she caught the cake" does not admit

"with that")

6) Marker sensitive to gender and number of antecedent = Full

pronominal feature, like il quale (masc.sing.), i quali (masc. pl.),

la quale (fem. sing.) le quali (fem. pl.) in Italian, my

mother-tongue, but also in French and German at least.



Within the semantics of prototypes, we would state that within the

same category some items are more or less central to the category, or

are good or bad representative of that category. In English, if we

only take the pronominal feature, we can say that “that” is not a

central representative of the relative marker, because of the presence

of markers of type 3, 4, and 5, which have a stronger pronoun-hood.



THE A-TAD-BIT-LESS COMPOSITE NATURE OF SUBORDINATORS

Along the same lines, though, if we tried to build a continuum for the

category “subordinator,” we would state that “that” as a relative

clause marker is definitely not prototypical of the category because

it has some pronoun-hood features though extremely light. But

interestingly enough, also the other “that,” the one traditionally

dubbed subordinator (as in “I think that you should go”) isn't a good

representative of the category either. The reason rests on the fact

that there is no other more “typical” subordinator that can be

dropped. Thus far I have tried to think of any example in which we can

drop subordinators such as “while,” “because,” “although,” “even

though,” “since” and didn't come up with anything. If you have any

example, it is more than welcome. Only in elliptical sentences,

subordinators can be dropped as in the following exchange:

A- Why didn't you go to the party?

B- [I didn't go to the party because] My car didn't start.



In this sense, one line of argument of Huddleston's seems to be rather

weak, because “that” as a relative clause marker becomes a

subordinator on the basis of a feature that is not so salient in

defining the category itself. It would be like saying that a rat is an

elephant because they are both gray, where “gray-ness” is not exactly

the most central and representative feature that characterizes either

an elephant or a rat. Nonetheless, in the semantics of prototypes we

could still maintain that there's some family resemblance that could

justify ascribing the relative “that” to the category subordinator. As

a matter of fact, also the relative “that” introduces a clause

subordinated to the main clause.



MY SUBSTITUTION TEST

My substitution test with “which” was not much aimed at pointing out

the similarity between the relative “that” and wh-markers. It was

rather aimed at pointing out the difference between relative “that”

and subordinator “that.”

The book that {which} is on the desk is very interesting.

They said that {*which} it is interesting.



When we have “that” as a relative marker the substitution is

structurally and semantically possible even though, according I do

agree that there are some differences. But the point is that when we

have “that” as a subordinator, the substitution is totally impossible.



AREN'T THERE TWO DIFFERENT SEMIOTIC REASONS FOR DROPPING THE TWO “THATs”?

The dropping itself of “that” as a relative marker (when in

restrictive clauses and not in subject position) and “that” as a

complementizer seems to be justified by two different semiotic

reasons.



- Dropping “that” as a relative marker

The possibility is ingrained in language because there are languages

that can do perfectly well without any relative clause marker (at

least Japanese). Moreover, in English this dropping is also possible

when the marker replaces the subject of the relative clause provided

that it is in the passive voice and the auxiliary “to be” is also

dropped (some linguists call them whiz-clauses):

The rooms [that were] reserved for the trip are very expensive.



- Dropping “that” as a complementizer

This omissible complementizer introduces the direct object of the main

clause and often the verb can be followed by direct speech:

They maintained

They said

They believed                     (that) it was the most useful action

They doubted

They thought





Neither direct objects nor direct speech are introduced by any marker.

So it is possible that, cognitively speaking, the absence of “that” as

a subordinator does not create any difficulty/ambiguity in our

perception of the sentence.

Notice that in the last sentence (“It is possible that the absence of

“that” as a subordinator does not create....”) the extraposition of

the subject creates still a different behavior of “that,” which, I

think but am not sure, cannot be omitted:



- That the absence of “that”as a subordinator does not create…. is possible

- It is possible that the absence of “that” as a subordinator does not

create …..

- *?It is possible the absence of “that” as a subordinator does not create



Ciao,

Sergio







2013/5/8 Stahlke, Herbert <[log in to unmask]>:

> Sergio,

>

> You're in the midst of a long, intermittent discussion of the status of "that" in relative clauses.  Grammarians from Otto Jespersen to Rodney Huddleston have argued that relative "that" is, in fact, a subordinator and not a pronoun.  The substitution you suggest is misleading, because that-relatives behave differently from wh-relatives, in ways I can't go into just now.

>

> Herb

>

> Herbert F. W. Stahlke, Ph.D.

> Emeritus Professor of English

> Ball State University

> Muncie, IN  47306

> [log in to unmask]

> ________________________________________

> From: Assembly for the Teaching of English Grammar [[log in to unmask]] on behalf of sergio [[log in to unmask]]

> Sent: Wednesday, May 08, 2013 1:42 AM

> To: [log in to unmask]

> Subject: Re: relative "that" revisited

>

> Dear Dr. Stankle,

>

> I might be missing the point and for the sake of my better

> understanding, I was wondering whether a simple substitution test is

> possible here.

>

> "He avoids whatever roads might cross this desolate valley and stays

> on the open land, so there's no risk of turning a bend and ramming

> head-on into innocent motorists, with all the physical and moral

> consequences that(replace it with "which") would ensue."

>

> Therefore in "...with all the physical and moral consequences WHICH

> would ensue", the original "that" is a relative pronoun referring to

> "all the physical and moral consequences" and subject of "[THEY=the

> consequences] would ensue". It is not a subordinating conjunction as

> in,

> "I think that they would ensue"

> because here "which" cannot substitute "that".

>

> Does this make any sense?

>

> Sergio Pizziconi

>

> 2013/5/8 Stahlke, Herbert <[log in to unmask]>:

>> I came upon an interesting "garden path" sentence today in Dean Koontz's One

>> Door away from Heaven (Bantam 2001), p. 287.

>>

>> "He avoids whatever roads might cross this desolate valley and stays on the

>> open land, so there's no risk of turning a bend and ramming head-on into

>> innocent motorists, with all the physical and moral consequences that would

>> ensue."

>>

>> When I got to the last three words, I anticipated that "that" would be a

>> pronoun referring to "turning a bend and ramming head-on into innocent

>> motorists," and I expected a verb like "entail."  However, the verb "ensue"

>> stopped me cold and forced me to reread and interpret "that" as a

>> subordinating conjunction.  We've discussed that status of "that" in

>> relative clauses at some length, and I've taken the position that it's not a

>> pronoun but rather a subordinating conjunction with no referential function.

>> In this case, one could write, "that that would entail," but Koontz is a

>> better writer than that.  The choice, however, is between a demonstrative

>> pronoun and a subordinator.  The fact that they can be used together

>> supports the claim that they are two different words with very different

>> functions.  Very likely the preference for only the demonstrative in this

>> case, rather than both, is an example of haplology.

>>

>> Herb

>>

>> Herbert F. W. Stahlke, Ph.D.

>> Emeritus Professor of English

>> Ball State University

>> Muncie, IN  47306

>> [log in to unmask]

>> To join or leave this LISTSERV list, please visit the list's web interface

>> at: http://listserv.muohio.edu/archives/ateg.html and select "Join or leave

>> the list"

>>

>> Visit ATEG's web site at http://ateg.org/

>

> To join or leave this LISTSERV list, please visit the list's web interface at:

>      http://listserv.muohio.edu/archives/ateg.html

> and select "Join or leave the list"

>

> Visit ATEG's web site at http://ateg.org/

>

>

> To join or leave this LISTSERV list, please visit the list's web interface at:

>      http://listserv.muohio.edu/archives/ateg.html

> and select "Join or leave the list"

>

> Visit ATEG's web site at http://ateg.org/



To join or leave this LISTSERV list, please visit the list's web interface at:

     http://listserv.muohio.edu/archives/ateg.html

and select "Join or leave the list"



Visit ATEG's web site at http://ateg.org/










ATOM RSS1 RSS2